Easy as 1, 2, 3 ? Wittgenstein on counting

“A B C

It’s easy as, 1 2 3

As simple as, do re mi

A B C, 1 2 3

Baby, you and me girl”

Door Catarina Dutilh Novaes

45 years ago, Michael Jackson and his troupe of brothers famously claimed that counting is easy peasy. But how easy is it really? (We’ll leave aside the matter of the purported simplicity of A B C and do re mi for present purposes!)

Counting and basic arithmetic operations are often viewed as paradigmatic cases of ‘easy’ mental operations. It might seem that we are all ‘born’ with the innate ability for basic arithmetic, given that we all seem to engage in the practice of counting effortlessly. However, as anyone who has cared for very young children knows, teaching a child how to count is typically a process requiring relentless training, involving a host of practices such as that of physically pointing at objects and for each object enunciating a numeral. The child may well know how to recite the order of numbers (‘one, two, three…’), but from that to associating each of them to specific quantities is a big step. Even when they start getting the hang of it, they typically do well with small quantities (say, up to 3), but things get mixed up when it comes to counting more items. For example, they need to resist the urge to point at the same item more than once in the counting process, something that is in no way straightforward! 

The later Wittgenstein was acutely aware of how much training is involved in mastering the practice of counting and basic arithmetic operations. (Recall that he was a schoolteacher for many years in the 1920s!) Indeed, counting and adding objects can be described as a specific and rather peculiar language game which must be learned by training, and which raises all kinds of philosophical questions pertaining to what it is exactly that we are doing when we count things. Perhaps my favorite passage in the whole of the Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics is #37 in part I:

Put two apples on a bare table, see that no one comes near them and nothing shakes the table; now put another two apples on the table; now count the apples that are there. You have made an experiment; the result of the counting is probably 4. (We should present the result like this: when, in such-and-such circumstances, one puts first 2 apples and then another 2 on a table, mostly none disappear and none get added.) And analogous experiments can be carried out, with the same result, with all kinds of solid bodies.—This is how our children learn sums; for one makes them put down three beans and then another three beans and then count what is there. If the result at one time were 5, at another 7 (say because, as we should now say, one sometimes got added, and one sometimes vanished of itself), then the first thing we said would be that beans were no good for teaching sums. But if the same thing happened with sticks, fingers, lines and most other things, that would be the end of all sums.

“But shouldn’t we then still have 2 + 2 = 4?”—This sentence would have become unusable.

What Wittgenstein seems to be saying here, among other things, is that the practice of counting is useful only insofar as certain conditions are in place, in particular the discreteness (so that they can be counted) and perdurance of objects, which ensures that collections of objects have a stable numerical value when no external interference occurs. If objects would regularly fuse and multiply, or appear and disappear spontaneously, then counting and doing sums would not be a very meaningful, useful – or usable! – practice at all. This also means that the practice of counting is not a purely arbitrary construction; its fruitfulness depends crucially on how things happen to be in the world.

In fact, the stability of objects in this sense may be a necessary condition for the meaningfulness of the practice of counting, but it still does not seem to be a sufficient condition. Recent anthropological work by Pica and others argues that some tribes in the Amazon speak languages that do not have words for counting beyond 2 or 3, as beyond that counting words are not used in any consistent way. In terms of the metaphysical properties of objects, members of these cultures live the same world as ours, and yet for various reasons the need for the practice of counting seems not to have emerged in these cultures. Indeed, when given tests with simple arithmetical operations with exact quantities, members of this culture perform ‘poorly’ for our standards; this seems like a clear win for Wittgenstein on counting. (Notice that they perform just fine when it comes to tasks involving approximations.)

Recent developmental work on numerical cognition also seems to lend support to the Wittgensteinian view of counting as training. While there is still much debate on the extent to which infants and very young children have some ‘innate’ sense of quantities, quite some results suggest that mastery of the practice of counting in exactly the way we do it – that is, based on the concept of a linear progression of the natural numbers, where the difference between 1 and 2 is ‘the same’ as the difference between 9 and 10 – requires extensive training, and becomes fully established only once children have been suitably ‘indoctrinated’, typically by formal schooling. (note that my MA course ‘Wittgenstein on the barest essentials’ in the third quarter will focus on these and other issues; so if you liked what you’ve just read, come join us!)

The upshot is thus that, pace the Jackson brothers, there is nothing easy about 1, 2, 3 – something that the later Wittgenstein already knew all too well, and which has been recently corroborated by anthropological as well as developmental research on numerical cognition. To be sure, there are still competing theories on numerical cognition among psychologists and cognitive scientists, and some of them are closer to the Wittgensteinian conception of counting as a language game requiring extensive training than others. But many of Wittgenstein’s insights have been borne out by recent research, which means that they provide an empirically-motivated starting point for a fully-fledged philosophical account of counting and basic arithmetic.

“He doesn’t want to prove this or that, but to find out how things really are.” (Russell on Wittgenstein) Wittgenstein’s approach to philosophy consists in asking very basic, fundamental questions, and this holds in particular of his approach to logic, language, and mathematics: not to offer technical proofs but rather to raise basic questions such as “what is a proof?”, “what is counting?”, “what makes a proposition meaningful/true?” For Wittgenstein, to understand the complex cases, we first need to understand the basics of the simple cases — which turn out to be everything but simple or straightforward. But the goal of the course will not be exclusively historical/exegetical; arguably, Wittgenstein asked all the right questions about logic, language, and mathematics, and thus a discussion of his texts should prompt further philosophical reflection.


Catarina Dutilh Novaes is associate professor and Rosalind Franklin Fellow at the Department of Theoretical Philosophy of the Faculty of Philosophy in Groningen. She is interested in a wide range of philosophical topics, and much prefers when philosophical analysis is embedded in empirical data. She is still learning how to count, and hopes that Wittgenstein will be of some help.

 

 

 

Facebooktwittertumblrmail

Dit artikel is geschreven door een gastauteur. Schrijf ook voor de Qualia! Kopij kan gestuurd worden naar de redactie via fil-qualia@rug.nl.

Geef een reactie

Het e-mailadres wordt niet gepubliceerd. Verplichte velden zijn gemarkeerd met *